Stewart/Colbert’s Rally to Restore Sanity and the Psychology of Moderates

September 21st, 2010 by Ravi Iyer

As someone who is interested in promoting civility and reason in politics, I have been really excited over the past few days by Jon Stewart’s announcement of a Rally to Restore Sanity (“Million Moderate March”), coupled with Stephen Colbert’s satirical “March to Keep Fear Alive”.  The below video, where the announcement is made, is well worth watching, if only for it’s entertainment value.

The Daily Show With Jon Stewart Mon – Thurs 11p / 10c
Rally to Restore Sanity
www.thedailyshow.com
Daily Show Full Episodes Political Humor Tea Party

Normally, we look at our yourmorals.org data in terms of liberals and conservatives, but what can we say about moderates.  In many instances (e.g. Measures of general moral or political positions using Moral Foundations or Schwartz Values), moderates score between liberals and conservatives.  However, there are a couple interesting findings about moderates in our data that might be of interest.

First, moderates are less engaged in politics.  This isn’t a particularly controversial finding as research in social psychology shows that extreme attitudes are more resistant to change and more likely to predict behavior.  Moderates are defined by their lack of extremity and this lack of extremity predicts a disinterest in politics and lack of desire to engage in political action.

As such, it is not surprising that, as Stewart notes, the only voices which often get heard are the loudest voices.  Shouting hurts your throat and moderates are unwilling to pay that price.  But couched in terms of entertainment and comedy?  Maybe that will spur moderates to attend in a way that an overtly political/partisan event could never do.

Going a bit deeper, the other area where moderates score differently than liberals and conservatives is in terms of their willingness to moralize issues.  Moderates are less likely to frame issues as moral and less likely to be moral maximizers. Morality can be a great force for good, but there is also research on idealistic evil and the dark side of moral conviction.  You’ll notice that while liberals and conservatives moralize individual issues in the below graph at different levels, the extremes generally moralize issues more than moderates or less extreme partisans.  It’s worth noting I recently attended a talk by Linda Skitka where her team found (in China) that high moralization scores predict willingness to spy on and censor people with opposing viewpoints.

Moderates also score lower on a general (not issue specific) measure of moral maximizing.  Below is a graph of scores on individual moral maximizing questions.  Again, a lot of good may be done in the name of morality and moral maximizers may be less willing to let people starve or let injustice stand.  However, a lot of bad may be done in the name of morality as well and “never settling” for imperfect moral outcomes seems like a recipe for the kind of political ugliness that we see these days.  Moderates appear willing to accept imperfection in the moral realm.

Maximizing is a concept made popular by Barry Schwartz at Swarthmore in his book, the Paradox of Choice and his TED talk.  The argument isn’t that high standards are a bad thing…but that at some point, there is a level where overly high standards have negative consequences.  The point that Stewart and Colbert are making is that perhaps partisans have reached that point in our political dialogue, to the detriment of policy.

I probably won’t make it to DC, but I do plan on celebrating the Rally to Restore Sanity in some way, perhaps at a satellite event.  I am generally liberal and will be surrounded mainly (though not exclusively) by liberal friends.  It would be really easy to use the event as a time to mock and denigrate the extremity of the other side.  However, liberal moral absolutism has it’s dangers too.  For those of us who really want to restore sanity to political debate, it is an opportunity to be the change we want to see in the world and take a moment to reflect on how our political side can ‘take it down a notch for America’, rather than assuming that Stewart is talking to ‘them’.  And perhaps that begins with accepting some amount of moral imperfection.

– Ravi Iyer

Posted in civil politics, civility, hypermoralism, jon stewart, moral absolutism, news commentary, partisanship, political psychology, stephen colbert, yourmorals.org | 1 Comment »

Why do we study the psychology of libertarians?

August 28th, 2010 by Ravi Iyer

We recently submitted a paper for publication about libertarian morality, along with co-authors Spassena Koleva, Jesse Graham, Pete Ditto, and Jonathan Haidt.  The paper leverages our broad set of measures to tell a story about libertarians, which converges with previously reported findings about liberals and conservatives.  Specifically, all ideological groups demonstrate the same patterns whereby preferences, emotions and dispositions lead to an attraction to corresponding values and ideological narratives.  For example, liberals have greater feelings of empathy and are therefore more likely to moralize harm and be attracted to an ideology which prioritizes this moralization.  Libertarians moralize liberty, both economic liberty, similar to conservatives, and lifestyle liberty, similar to liberals.

Libertarians believe in the importance of individual liberty, a belief that may be related to lower levels of agreeableness and higher scores on a measure of psychological reactance (e.g. “regulations trigger a sense of resistance in me”).  They moralize concerns about harm less than liberals, in part because they have lower levels of empathy .  They moralize principles concerning being a group member (obeying authority and being loyal) less than conservatives in part because they have less attachment to the groups around them.

If you want to read more about what the paper, says, you can click here or download the paper here, but right now, I’d like to focus on why we wrote the paper, as I have previously written about how people are attracted to why you write things as much as what you write.

Of course, some part of paper writing is driven by curiosity and the practical desire to publish.  But in writing this paper, I have undergone my own personal intellectual journey, and I’m hopeful that others may have a similar experience. A lot of my impression of libertarianism was previously shaped by images of the Tea Party (who aren’t necessarily libertarians after all) and I thought of libertarians as uncaring, from my liberal perspective, in that they typically don’t support progressive taxes and social programs. The original title of the paper was “the Search for Libertarian Morality”, implying that libertarians are potentially amoral, and in retrospect showing my own ideological bias.

But as I read more about libertarian philosophy and looked more carefully at the data, I found that libertarians do indeed have a coherent moral code, that simply differs from my own. Like my liberal leanings, which have some relation to my dispositions and preferences, libertarians also moralize their preferences and dispositions, in ways that mirror my own processes. For example, liberals and libertarians both score high on desire for new experiences and stimulation, which may be a common reason why both groups tend to emphasize individual choice over group solidarity, compared to conservatives, as cohesive groups can limit choice.  Libertarians may be less moved by emotions such as disgust and empathy, which may lead them to moralize certain situations less than others.  But who am I to say that my moral compass is any better or worse than theirs, given my view that at some level, the basis for my liberal moral compass is driven by subjective sentiment.  I previously wrote about the dangers of liberal moral absolutism, and villainizing libertarians for not sharing my particular vision of morality would be a step down that road.

Why do we seek to publicize this paper?  In a time when partisanship dominates, policy suffers,  and people on both sides of the aisle villainize the other side, it is our hope that with greater understanding comes greater acceptance. We may not all agree about the relative merits of empathy, disgust, or reactance as moral emotions…but we all have some level of all of these emotions and can respect principles born out of these.  Even liberals can find things so disgusting that they are seen as wrong, and conservatives actually give a lot of money to the poor.  In attributing moral disagreements to dispositions, largely out of our control, perhaps we can learn to see others as different and attracted to other positive moral principles, rather than amoral and oblivious to the moral principles that are important to us.

– Ravi Iyer

Posted in civil politics, differences between republicans and democrats, liberals and conservatives, libertarians, moral emotions, moral psychology, partisanship, political psychology, psychological reactance, yourmorals.org | 4 Comments »

Having your cake … and finally eating it too.

August 14th, 2010 by Brad

[This is the third (and final?) installment of a three part series of posts investigating the possibility of using the YourMorals data to make inferences about the general population. In this installment, we finally make the leap.]

In my previous posts, I’ve  discussed the many potential difficulties in using an entirely self-selected internet sample for inferences about general population parameters (whether or not a particular state or congressional district scores higher than another in terms of its moral foundations) as opposed to the intra-individual comparisons that are the bread and butter of psychologists (like how the foundations tend to correlate with ideology). I think that I have shown that the raw data are unsuitable for talking about the general population. The sample is demographically unrepresentative (see here) and somewhat attitudinally unrepresentative (see here).

What we need is a method to correct for the biases in the sample. Enter Multilevel Regression with Poststratification (or Mr. P as he is affectionately known to statisticians).*

[For those uninterested in the technical aspects of modeling, skip down to the maps below]

Multilevel Regression with Poststratification proceeds in (basically) three steps. First ,we construct a model to obtain the expected values of the variable of interest as a function of variables that we know the underlying population values for (typically this means only items that show up in the Census – geography, age, education, income, race, gender, maybe a few others).

Second, we use the model to predict the expected value of the variable of interest for each combination of variables (or cells) in the model. For example, if the model used four regions (Northeast, South, Midwest, West), three categories of age (18-30, 31-60, 61+), three categories of education (HS, College, Graduate), two categories of income (Less than $50k, More than $50k), two categories of race (white, non-white), and gender as predictors, there would be a total of 4*3*3*2*2*2 = 288 cells. From a 18 year old male with a HS degree or less who makes less than $50k is white and lives in Maine to a 75 year old female with a PhD making more than $50k is Asian and lives in New Mexico.  All individuals in the sample fit into one (and only one) of the cells defined by the combinations of predictors in the model. Many of the cells will be empty. In cells where there is no data, the model borrows statistical power from the other cells to come up with an expected value for every cell.

Finally, we weight each of the estimated cell values by the proportion of individuals in the population to come up with predictions for the geographic regions of interest. In this case, we would have predictions for each region.**

The map above (click on the image for a better view) plots the predictions from the MRP estimates of the difference between the liberal and conservative foundations for each congressional district. Districts in which YourMorals users valued the two “liberal” foundations (H and F) more than the three conservative foundations (I,A,P) are shown in dark green, and those districts cluster in the regions that we know to be the most liberal parts of the country: the North East, and the West Coast (excluding the agricultural parts of California). The districts within which YourMorals users gave the most conservative pattern (IAP > HF) are shown in red, and these districts fall overwhelmingly within the South.

One way to test the validity of these measures of district level foundations is to compare them to observable characteristics of the districts. One ready comparison we can make is to the district’s share of the vote for Obama in the 2008 presidential election.

The figure below shows the simple bivariate relationship between each foundation and vote for Obama. In every case, we see the expected relationships. Districts that scored more highly on the Harm and Fairness foundations were more likely to go for Obama in the election. On the other hand, there is a strong negative relationship between a district’s score on the Purity foundation and its vote for Obama.

Interestingly in many cases (especially the harm and authority foundations), there appears to be a significant “kink” in the fitted line at the midpoint of some of the foundations. Districts that score highly on the harm foundation (or those with low scores on the authority foundation) are associated with increased showings for Obama, but that relationship dissipates after the mid point of the foundation is crossed (all foundation scores are measured in standard deviation units). This is an aspect of the data that deserves further attention, but I’ve run out of time and space to do so here.

Multiple regression estimates confirm the overall story we see here in the bivariate plots. The estimated foundation scores seem to meaningfully correlate with real world phenomena. This bodes well for the validity of the measure and method.***

So, with a little work, it appears as if we can have our cake and eat it too when it comes to the YourMorals data. Scores on the foundations (after adjusting for the biases in the sample) are significantly related to district voting behavior.

*For a more detailed explanation of the methods involved see here. Also, Andrew Gelman and Jennifer Hill’s excellent book, Data Analysis using Regression and Multilevel/Hierarchical Models.

**I made an editorial decision not to include the details of the model and etc. as it didn’t seem of general interest. I’m more than happy to talk about it, but the post was getting wordy as it was.

*** The careful reader might well protest that the relationship we see in the figures presented is merely the product of the correlations with demography picked up from the MRP method. Since I used district demographics to adjust the scores obtained from the convenience sample, is it possible that the positive findings are simply a reflection of secondary correlations between the moral foundation scores and demographics? One easy way to test for this is to include demographic controls in the model. I was happy to see that none of the findings are substantially changed by including district demographics on the right hand side of the regression.

Posted in Uncategorized | No Comments »

I did not make a mistake in disagreeing with Haidt

August 13th, 2010 by PaulBloom

I appreciate Jonathan Haidt’s gracious and constructive response to my Nature paper, and I want to begin my reply by acknowledging my considerable debt to him. My own research into moral psychology got started when I was approached by David Pizarro, then a graduate student at Yale, concerning Jon’s classic 2001 Psychological Review article. David and I ended up writing a commentary on this article. Soon afterwards, I began a series of studies, with David and others, on the emotion of disgust, and here again Jon’s work was a catalyst and an inspiration. So I am a huge fan of Jonathan Haidt.

I do not, however, find his response convincing.

1. He has read my article as a critique of his Social Intuitionist Model. But it isn’t.  The point of the article was to argue for the importance of deliberative reasoning as an important aspect of moral psychology. I make this argument by outlining what I see as the modern consensus, which is, as Hume put it, that moral reasoning is “the slave of the passions”. Jon is probably the most prominent defender of this view, but other scholars who accept it, to varying degrees, are Stephen Stich, Philip Tetlock, Jesse Prinz, Philip Zimbardo, Drew Westin, and Michael Gazzaniga. When I begin my third paragraph by saying that I predict that “this theory” will be proven wrong, I’m referring to the reason-as-slave view, not any more specific theory.

In my second paragraph, I say that many psychologists think that reasoned arguments for moral beliefs are “mostly post-hoc justifications for gut reactions.” Then I write: “As the social psychologist Jonathan Haidt puts it, although we like to think of ourselves as judges, reasoning through cases according to deeply held principles, in reality we are more like lawyers, making arguments for positions that have already been established.” This is a perfectly accurate summary of his view from the 2001 paper, which is the paper of his that I cite.

2. It’s clear from the text, though, that Jon is categorized among those who endorse “the wholesale rejection of reason” in the formation of moral judgments. He is right to complain about this. The adjective was an overstatement of my part — one web dictionary says that it means “extensively and indiscriminately”, and it’s clear from his 2001 paper and elsewhere that Jon allows for some limited role of reason — and I apologize for it.

What about “rejection of reason”? Theories lie on a continuum and, in the space of views concerning morality, Jon’s theory in his 2001 paper really is famous in its rejection of reason. Jon seems to disagree; he modestly says “I merely rejected the worship of reasoning common in the Kohlbergian tradition.” – implying that his paper was nothing more than a gentle corrective to some over-zealous Kohlbergians! Well, I’ll leave this for the reader to judge. But I will point out that his title is “The emotional dog and the rational tail” And abstract begins with this:

Research on moral judgment has been dominated by rationalist models, in which moral judgment is thought to be caused by moral reasoning. Four reasons are given for considering the hypothesis that moral reasoning does not cause moral judgment; rather, moral reasoning is usually a post-hoc construction, generated after a judgment has been reached. The social intuitionist model is presented as an alternative to rationalist models. The model is a social model in that it de-emphasizes the private reasoning done by individuals, emphasizing instead the importance of social and cultural influences.

And the paper ends with this:

The time may be right, therefore, to take another look at Hume’s perverse thesis: that moral emotions and intuitions drive moral reasoning, just as a surely as a dog wags its tail.

3. There is a lot of the Social Intuitionist Theory that I agree with. But I think it is mistaken in the view that private moral deliberation is irrelevant and unimportant. On the contrary, I would argue that it’s a central aspect of our moral lives. David and I argued for this in our response to Jon’s 2001 article, and I’ve expanded on this point in my 2004 book and again in my Nature article. Jon begins his reply to me that “we agree on the basic story”. But, unless his views have changed, we don’t.

Posted in moral psychology | 12 Comments »

If You are Going to Criticize the Social Intuitionist Model, Please Don’t Repeat Paul Bloom’s Mistake

August 13th, 2010 by Jonathan Haidt

I love the work of developmental psychologist Paul Bloom. He and I have similar interests, similar ways of thinking, and even similar birthdays. When it appears that we disagree, as in the debate that first brought us into contact (over my 2001 “Emotional Dog” article and his response), it usually turns out that we agree on the basic story and differ only on the lessons we draw from that story. So I was quite surprised to read Paul’s prediction, in Nature, that my Social Intuitionist Model (on which I thought we largely agreed) will be proven wrong. Here’s the central passage:

All this leaves little room for rational deliberation in shaping our moral outlook. Indeed, many psychologists think that the reasoned arguments we make about why we have certain beliefs are mostly post-hoc justifications for gut reactions. As the social psychologist Jonathan Haidt puts it, although we like to think of ourselves as judges, reasoning through cases according to deeply held principles, in reality we are more like lawyers, making arguments for positions that have already been established. This implies we have little conscious control over our sense of right and wrong. I predict that this theory of morality will be proved wrong in its wholesale rejection of reason.   Emotional responses alone cannot explain one of the most interesting aspects of human nature: that morals evolve.

I have underlined the two main mistakes Bloom makes in setting up his difference with me. I’d like to correct them here

1) The “wholesale rejection of reason”

I have never engaged in a “wholesale rejection of reason.” Four of the six links in the Social Intuitionist model are kinds of reasoning. I merely rejected the worship of reasoning common in the Kohlbergian tradition. I took seriously the research on motivated reasoning and the confirmation bias, which show that, just as David Hume said, reasoning is extremely effective as a servant, but rather ineffective as a tool for discovering the truth, at least when carried out by individuals. (A forthcoming review article on the “argumentative function of reasoning” will make this case far better than I did.) But I have always made it clear that reasoning is carried out for a purpose, and that purpose is to influence other people, particularly by triggering moral intuitions in them. For example:

The discussion thus far may have given the impression that the model dismisses reasoning as post-hoc rationalization (link 2). However it must be stressed that four of the six links in the model are reasoning links, and three of these links (3, 5, and 6) are hypothesized to have real causal effects on moral judgment. Link 3, the reasoned persuasion link, says that people’s (ex post facto) moral reasoning can have a causal effect – on other people’s intuitions. In the social intuitionist view moral judgment is not just a single act that occurs in a single person’s mind. It is an ongoing process, often spread out over time and over multiple people. Reasons and arguments can circulate and affect people, even if individuals rarely engage in private moral reasoning for themselves.  (Haidt, 2001, p. 828)

2) “Emotional response alone cannot explain…”

I fully agree with Bloom that emotions cannot be the whole story of morality. That’s why I shifted from talking about emotions in the 1990s to talking about intuitions, which are clearly a form of cognition, in the 2000s. It’s true that I used the phrase “the emotional dog,” which I thought sounded better than “the intuitive dog.” But I stated clearly in that paper, and many others, that the key terms in the debate are “intuition” and “reasoning,” which are both forms of cognition:

It must be stressed that the contrast of intuition and reasoning is not the contrast of emotion and cognition. Intuition, reasoning, and the appraisals contained in emotions (Frijda, 1986; Lazarus, 1991) are all forms of cognition. Rather, the words “intuition” and “reasoning” are intended to capture the contrast made by dozens of philosophers and psychologists between two kinds of cognition. The most important distinctions (see Table 1) are that intuition occurs quickly, effortlessly, and automatically, such that the outcome but not the process is accessible to consciousness, while reasoning occurs more slowly, requires some effort, and involves at least some steps that are accessible to consciousness. (Haidt, 2001, p. 815)

Of course, even intuitions, which are much more common and flexible than emotions, are not the whole story in the SIM. They’re just most of the story. They’re where the action is. So if you want to produce social change, you’ve got to change intuitions.

Oddly, Bloom uses narrative and story-telling as examples of the sorts of processes that are powerful in producing moral change. But these are exactly the sorts of processes that the SIM emphasizes, because stories and narrative are so effective at triggering intuitions. In order to contradict the SIM he’d need to show that logical reasoning (which does not appeal to emotions and intuitions) is often the cause of social change. Instead he states that “Humans are natural story tellers, and use narrative to influence others, particularly their own children.” But narrative is a crucial part of SIM, which Craig Joseph and I have linked to virtue ethics:

Moral education, on our account, is a matter of linking up the innate intuitions and virtues already learned with a skill that one wants to encourage. Parents and educators should therefore recognize the limits of the ‘direct route’ to moral education. It is helpful to espouse rules and principles, but only as an adjunct to more indirect approaches, which include immersing children in environments that are rich in stories and examples that adults interpret with emotion. Those stories and examples should trigger the innate moral modules, if possible, and link them to broader virtues and principles. (Haidt & Joseph, 2004, p. 65)

It seems, therefore, that once again, Paul Bloom and I basically agree on the outlines of moral psychology. We also agree that moral change is possible, particularly when gifted orators and story tellers — such as Martin Luther King Jr. — can create a new narrative and trigger supporting intuitions. In fact, I concluded my 2007 Science article with this paragraph, which would have been right at home in Bloom’s Nature piece:

Yet even though morality is partly a game of self-promotion, people do sincerely want peace, decency, and cooperation to prevail within their groups. And because morality may be as much a product of cultural evolution as genetic evolution, it can change substantially in a generation or two. For example, as technological advances make us more aware of the fate of people in faraway lands, our concerns expand and we increasingly want peace, decency, and cooperation to prevail in other groups, and in the human group as well. (Haidt, 2007, p. 1001)

So please. go out and buy Bloom’s fascinating new book, How Pleasure Works. Read his wonderful work on how the harm foundation is already operational in 6-month-old babies. But don’t make the mistake that he made, and that so many of my critics make, in assuming that I’m an emotivist who denies either the existence of reasoning or its importance for social change. We reason often, in order to persuade people.  We just don’t do it often, or well, as part of our own private search for moral truth.

–Jon Haidt

[To read Paul Bloom’s response, click here]

=====================================================

P.S., Here are three additional quotes that I hope potential critics will read before accusing me of siding with “emotion” versus “cognition,” or claiming that social change is impossible because we are “prisoners of our emotions.”

Link 5, the reasoned judgment link, recognizes that a person could, in principle, simply reason her way to a judgment that contradicts her initial intuition. The literature on everyday reasoning (Kuhn, 1991) suggests that such an ability may be common only among philosophers, who have been extensively trained and socialized to follow reasoning even to very disturbing conclusions (as in the case of Socrates, or the more recent works of Derek Parfit and Peter Singer). Yet the fact that there are at least a few people among us who can reach such conclusions on their own, and then argue for them eloquently (link 3), means that pure moral reasoning can play a causal role in the moral life of a society. (Haidt, 2001, p. 829)

The social intuitionist model also offers more general advice for improving moral judgment. If the principal difficulty in objective moral reasoning is the biased search for evidence (Kunda, 1990; Perkins, Farady, & Bushey, 1991), then people should take advantage of the social persuasion link (link 4) and get other people to help them improve their reasoning. By seeking out discourse partners who are respected for their wisdom and openmindedness, and by talking about the evidence, justifications, and mitigating factors involved in a potential moral violation, people can help trigger a variety of conflicting intuitions in each other. If more conflicting intuitions are triggered, the final judgment is likely to be more nuanced and ultimately more reasonable. The social intuitionist model, therefore, is not an anti-rationalist model. It is a model about the complex and dynamic ways that intuition, reasoning, and social influences interact to produce moral judgment. (Haidt, 2001, p. 829)

Affective reactions push, but they do not absolutely force. We can all think of times when we deliberated about a decision and went against our first (often selfish) impulse, or when we changed our minds about a person…. There are at least three ways we can override our immediate intuitive responses. We can use conscious verbal reasoning, such as considering the costs and benefits of each course of action. We can reframe a situation and see a new angle or consequence, thereby triggering a second flash of intuition that may compete with the first. And we can talk with people who raise new arguments, which then trigger in us new flashes of intuition followed by various kinds of reasoning. The social intuitionist model includes separate paths for each of these three ways of changing one’s mind, but it says that the first two paths are rarely used, and that most moral change happens as a result of social interaction. Other people often influence us, in part by presenting the counterevidence we rarely seek out ourselves. (Haidt, 2007 p. 999)

[To read Paul Bloom’s response, click here]

Posted in moral psychology | 9 Comments »

Moral Beauty, Politics, Gender, and Personality

August 9th, 2010 by Rhett

To engage with moral beauty means to see the beauty of virtues in others (and perhaps in ourselves).  As Joe Sachs has argued, Aristotle in the Nichomachean Ethics has described the virtues as the signs of beauty. In Sach’s translation of the NE Aristotle says that a virtue is “for the sake of the beautiful, for this is the end of virtue” (1115 b, 12-13), and that philanthropy is “for the sake of the beautiful, for this is common to the virtues” (1122 b, 7-8).

How is the quality of being engaged by moral beauty related to political ideology, gender, and various personality constructs, moral foundations, and values? To examine these questions the Engagement with Beauty Scale (EBS) was placed on YourMorals.org in May 2009 and 5,039 participants completed it by April 19, 2010. The EBS is a 14-item self-report scale comprised of three subscales: engagement with natural beauty (α = .81), engagement with artistic beauty (α = .86), and engagement with moral beauty (α = .91); summing those 3 subscales yields an EBS total score (α = .90).  The participants who took these measures are 52% women; 83% Americans; and had a mean age of 40.0 (SD = 15.9) (all the data reported in the table below had similar demographics).

Moral Beauty and Politics

I anticipated a substantial relationship between political ideology and engagement with beauty because previous studies with the Big 5 showed openness predicts both political liberalism and appreciation of beauty. However, the YourMorals.org data with a 7-point political ideology scale (1 = very liberal; 7 = very conservative) showed a very low correlation with the moral beauty subscale: -.05 (n = 4,672, p < .001).  The negative sign on the .05 indicates a slight liberal leaning for engaging with moral beauty, but primarily it shows that being engaged by the moral beauty of others is unrelated to political ideology. As an aside, the EBS engagement with natural beauty subscale x political ideology had a r = -.10 (p < .001) and the EBS engagement with artistic beauty subscale x political ideology had a r = -.19 (p < .001).

Moral Beauty and Gender

Women (N = 2,299) scored higher (M = 33.9; SD = 7.2) than men (N = 2,397; M = 30.6; SD = 8.3) on the EBS moral beauty subscale; t(4694) = 14.37, p < .001, d = .42; and in fact scored higher on the engagement with natural and artistic beauty subscales as well.  This aligns with Haidt and Keltner’s brief review of gender issues in their chapter on appreciation of beauty and excellence in Character Strengths and Virtues; it also reinforces a previous study I’ve done with the EBS which also found women scoring somewhat higher than men. That men tend to score lower on engagement with beauty than women may lend some empirical support to Wendy Steiner’s assertion, in her Venus in Exile. The Rejection of Beauty in 20th-Century Art, that artists and academics of the 20th century denigrated the classic feminine qualities of sympathy, empathy, and love that are associated with beauty in favor of the power and horror of a masculine sublime.

Because of the substantial gender difference (d = .42) on the EBS moral beauty subscale I partialled out gender in regard to correlations with a variety of relevant measures – see the table below.

What predicts engaging with moral beauty?

Scale Correlation with Moral Beauty Engagement After partialling out gender
Moral Foundations  Questionnaire  (n = 4,730)
Harm .36 ** .30 **
Fairness .20 ** .18 **
Authority .07 ** .09 **
Ingoup .10 ** .12 **
Purity .15 ** .16 **
Big 5 (n = 3,495)
Agreeableness .35 ** .34 **
Openness .17 ** .18 **
Extraversion .19 ** .18 **
Neuroticism .01 -.01
Conscientiousness .07 ** .05 *
IRI (n = 1,433)
Empathic Concern .59 ** .57 **
Perspective Taking .35 ** .33 **
Fantasy .32 ** .29 **
Personal Distress .02 -.01
Schwartz Values (n = 2,594)
Universalism .34 ** .32 **
Benevolence .44 ** .42 **
Self-Direction .08 ** .07 **
Stimulation .08 ** .09 **
Tradition .19 ** .21 **
Conformity .19 ** .20 **
Security .17 ** .17 **
Power -.07 ** -.05 *
Achievement .05 * .05 *
Hedonism -.07 ** -.06 *
Spirituality .41 ** .41 **
Heartland Forgiveness (n = 84)
Forgive Self .16 .13
Forgive others .51 ** .50 **
Forgive Situations .37 ** .36 **
Total Forgiveness score .44 ** .43 **
GQ-6 Gratitude (n = 1,006) .42 ** .41 **
Scales that were not substantial predictors
Satisfaction with Life (n = 2,291) .14 ** .12 **
Disgust Scale-Revised (n = 4,464) .05 * .06 **

Note: *p<.01, **p<.001; n indicates the number of participants in the partial correlation analysis.

Summary

As can be seen in the table above, partialling out gender had very little influence on the various relationships that engaging with moral beauty has with a variety variables. Being engaged by moral beauty predicts being concerned about caring for and preventing harm to others; being agreeable across situations; valuing universalism, benevolence, and spirituality; being grateful for the small and large bounties in life; and being forgiving of and having empathy for others.

Feel free to complete an EBS at YourMorals.org and see your score.  Also, to access a copy of the EBS and related papers, see http://www.lcsc.edu/diessner/.

–Rhett Diessner

Posted in big 5, empathy, liberals, moral emotions, moral foundations, moral psychology, openness to experience, positive psychology, yourmorals.org | 3 Comments »

Having your cake… part 2

August 3rd, 2010 by Brad

[This is the second post in a series of posts dealing with the representativeness of the YourMorals data, see here to read the first post]

Last time, I gave a broad overview of the descriptive representation of the YourMorals dataset. In a nutshell, we discovered that the YourMorals respondents were much more educated, more likely to self-identify as liberal, and more likely to be white than the population.

In this post, I will explore the question of whether the YourMorals respondents are representative of the population after we condition on observable characteristics. Put another way, would we expect two individuals, one randomly chosen from the population and one drawn from the YourMorals data, who share all the same demographic characteristics (age, race, education, political ideology, place of residence) to look the same in terms of their scores on the Moral Foundations Questionnaire?

To conduct this kind of analysis, first we need a benchmark against which to compare the YourMorals data. As I mentioned in my previous post, the gold standard is a randomly drawn sample from the population. Luckily, we have just such a survey. Prior to the 2008 election, Knowledge Networks* fielded a version of the Moral Foundations Questionnaire to a representative sample of the U.S. population. This provides a good point of comparison for our (much larger) convenience sample.

The first task is to process the YourMorals data so that it looks more like the general population. I used a basic sample matching technique to match individuals from the YourMorals data and the Knowledge Networks data. This is a crude technique, but effective. Basically for each individual in the Knowledge Networks sample (the “match target”), I found an individual (or individuals) in the YourMorals data that matched the demographic information for the “match target.” These cases then become the comparison group. After the samples have been balanced in terms of observable characteristics, any differences we observe between the two can be ascribed to the compounding factors that we cannot observe.**

The following figures show how the distributions of the matched YourMorals data compares with the distributions in the sample from Knowledge Networks. The dashed lines show the distribution for Knowledge Networks, the solid lines represent the YourMorals data.

Figure 1

The distributions of the foundations in the two data sources look very similar for the Fairness/Reciprocity foundation, but for all of the others, there are significant differences between the YourMorals and the Knowledge Networks respondents.

A little more digging reveals some interesting patterns. Splitting up the sample by ideology yields:

Liberals:

Figure 2 - Liberals only

Conservatives:

Figure 3 - Conservatives onlyTwo of the foundations seem to stand out in these comparisons. Liberals in the YourMorals data are particularly low on the Purity foundation (when compared against liberals in the Knowledge Networks data), and conservatives from the YourMorals sample seem to score lower on the Harm foundation. In both cases, YourMorals liberals seem more like population liberals on the first two foundations (Harm and Fairness), and the conservatives in the sample seem more like population conservatives on the last two foundations (Authority and Purity). No matter how the data is cut, the YourMorals sample seems to score lower on the Ingroup foundation.

The comparisons between the general population sample and the convenience sample in this post raise some significant questions about the possibility of using the self-selected respondents in the YourMorals sample to make inferences about the population. These problems in the data are particularly evident in the Ingroup foundation, the purity foundation (for liberals), and the harm foundation (for conservatives).

As was the case with demographics, all is not lost. One last look at the data shows that again the foundations are more or less proportionally correct. Liberals score higher in on the Harm and Fairness foundations in relation to their scores on the other three, and conservatives show more or less equal scores across each of the foundations. The bar chart below shows the average scores of the foundations broken out by survey source (KN and YM for Knowledge Networks and YourMorals respectively) and ideology:

Figure 4

Next time, I’ll discuss how we might correct for some of these demographic and attitudinal biases in the data.

*For the uninitiated, Knowledge Networks is a survey research firm that has gone to great lengths to put together a panel of internet users that is nationally representative. They have recruited a large panel of individuals to take internet surveys. These individuals were generally contacted by telephone, and in cases where the respondent did not have internet access, Knowledge Networks provided access. See this link for more information.

**For a quick primer on the theory behind sample matching see this Wikipedia entry.  I am using exact matching on categories of age, race, education, ideology, and state of residence.

Posted in conservatives, liberals, Uncategorized | 2 Comments »
Tags: , ,

Having your cake and eating it too: Representativeness and the YourMorals Data

July 28th, 2010 by Brad

[This is the first in a several part series on creating representative samples from convenience sampling data]

Earlier Jon Haidt discussed the “problem” of representativeness of the YourMorals data and concluded that it wasn’t such a problem after all. Convenience samples drawn from the internet can produce reliable data. This is particularly true when we are more interested in taking valid measurements than in painting a representative picture of some underlying population.

But what if we would also like to know something about the underlying population? If we had data that were representative of the country as a whole, we would be able to ask a new set of questions. Does knowing where the states fall in terms of their Moral Foundations tell us anything about voting behavior? We might expect scores on the purity foundation to explain state-level attitudes about gay marriage or the fairness foundation to explain attitudes about tax policy. To answer these kinds of questions, we need representative samples (also see Jesse Graham’s comment in the above link).

In sampling theory, the gold standard is the probability sample. When all individuals in the population have a known (but not necessarily equal) probability of being included in the sampling frame, we can construct reliable estimates of the population parameters and, given sufficient sample size, be confident that these estimates are within some distance of the true values in the population. However, the central assumptions of sampling theory are violated in convenience sampling (but see this discussion of the representation problems in traditional “random” sample polls).

First, we would like to get a sense of how the YourMorals data stacks up against other population measures. We collected data on several demographic characteristics of individuals in the YourMorals dataset. We can easily compare these against population values collected from the census or other representative samples.

One area where we can clearly see the representation problems in the YourMorals data is self-reported ideology. Considering only U.S. respondents for the time being (as all of the following analyses do), recent national samples put the proportion of people who consider themselves “liberal” at between 18 and 22 per cent. In the YourMorals data, this figure is nearly 65 percent.* Given this skew in the data, we might be hesitant in trying to make inferences about the general population from a sample that looks so much different.

The figures below show how the YourMorals data compares with the population values across a handful of demographic and attitudinal variables.

Figure 1

Source: Pew Center for the People and the Press, 2001-2008

This figure shows how even with a significant intercept shift (almost 50 points), the rank ordering of the states stays pretty close to the same. This is encouraging as it means we are not drawing the same type of individual from each state. Put differently, knowing the state that an individual resides in tells us something about the probability that he or she identifies as a liberal. What we would not want to see here would be a horizontal line (indicating no relationship).

Figure 2

Source: American Community Survey, 2006-2008

Figure 3

Source: American Community Survey, 2006-2008

With race it is much the same story as ideology. For whites, there is a substantial intercept shift (almost 70 points), but states with larger white populations also are proportionally more white in the YourMorals data. The data for African Americans is noisier (there were fewer than 900 in the sample of over 60,000), but shows the same pattern. Here there is not a large intercept shift (as we have reached the floor of the data), but we see the same kind of increasing pattern.

Figure 4

Source: American Community Survey, 2006-2008

With respect to education, the data are further afield. The figure shows that the YourMorals sample is significantly more educated than the general population, but it becomes more difficult to draw a convincing trend line through the data. Individuals who came from states with higher levels of education were only marginally more likely to be highly educated themselves.

So where does all of this leave us? It is obvious from the plots that the individuals who self-selected into the YourMorals data look very different than the general population. It would clearly be inappropriate to use the raw data in trying to make inferences about the general population parameters (average levels of a particular foundation in a particular state, for example). The sample is much more liberal, highly educated, and white than the general population. But it is not as bad as it could be. The worst-case scenario would show uniformly weird sample across the states. Instead, what we saw in the figures above is a picture that is more-or-less proportionally correct. It is encouraging that the general relationships hold up.

All of this is not to say that we should throw out the analyses presented elsewhere in this blog and in publications based on the YourMorals data. If we condition on ideology (which we saw was particularly skewed) and make statements like “Liberals generally score higher than conservatives on the Harm/Care and Fairness/Reciprocity foundations,” we are probably treading on safe ground.

In the next few posts, I will be revisiting the question of how to construct a representative picture from a convenience sample.

*Beyond the obvious sampling issues, there are a few other problems with directly comparing the measure of ideology in YourMorals with that in nationally representative samples. First, there is a mode difference that could account for some of the discrepancy (although certainly not all or even a very significant portion of it). Another (and more serious) difference between nationally representative samples and the YourMorals data is the choice of a seven point scale rather than a five point scale. Five point scales are used more regularly in telephone samples with the options being “Very Conservative,” “Conservative,” “Moderate,” “Liberal,” and “Very Liberal.” The YourMorals data includes options for “Slightly liberal” and “Slightly Conservative” as well as “Libertarian” and “other” categories. The 65 percent figure lumps all of the “liberals” together. If you believe that the “slightly liberal” respondents might have self-identified as “Moderate” given fewer options, the proportion turns out to be just over 50.

Posted in Uncategorized, yourmorals.org | 3 Comments »
Tags: , ,

On Hyperpartisanship, Hypermoralism, and the Supernormal Stimuli of Modern Politics

July 23rd, 2010 by Ravi Iyer

Today’s lead story from Politico, The Age of Rage, probably summarizes a lot of what people think is wrong with politics. Rather than make good policy, politicians and media are more concerned with scoring points for their political ideology (hyperpartisanship). However, as the Politico article points out, their actions are largely driven by the general populace. Politicians and media reflect what people respond to, which happens to be hyperpartisanship, rather than causing the incivility we see.

…there are two big incentives that drive behavior at the intersection where politics meets media. One is public attention. The other is money. Experience shows there’s lots more of both to be had by engaging in extreme partisan behavior.

Fox News has soared on the strength of commentators like Bill O’Reilly and Sean Hannity, both of whom fanned the Sherrod story on the strength of the misleading Breitbart video. (A Fox senior executive, by contrast, urged the news side of the operation to get Sherrod’s response before going with the story, The Washington Post reported.) On the left, MSNBC is trying to emulate the success of primetime partisanship. Meanwhile, CNN, which has largely strived toward a neutral ideological posture, is battling steady relative declines in its audience.

If media executives hunger for ratings, politicians hunger for campaign cash and fame.

Obama put it best earlier this year, after Republican Rep. Joe Wilson of South Carolina shouted “you lie” during the president’s State of the Union speech. “The easiest way to get on television right now is to be really rude,” the president told ABC News.

Indeed, at first Wilson seemed embarrassed and apologized for his outburst. But within days, Wilson and his opponent were both flooded with campaign contributions; Wilson took in more than $700,000 in the immediate aftermath of his outburst and was a guest of honor on Hannity’s show and Fox News Sunday.

We reward politicians and news organizations, with our attention and our money, that engage in the very incivility that makes politics so ugly. This is true on both sides of the aisle.

At the recent meeting of the International Society of Political Psychology, Linda Skitka gave a talk which puts a lot of this in perspective for me. Her lab studies the dark side of moral conviction, which I call hypermoralism in the hope that the term catches on. Roy Baumeister studies a similar concept, idealistic evil. In Skitka’s talk, she demonstrates in a Chinese sample that political intolerance (e.g. “people with different positions than your own about this issue should be allowed to have their phones tapped by the Chinese government”) and social intolerance (e.g. “How willing would you be to have someone who did not share your views on this issue as a close personal friend?”) were best predicted by moral conviction (e.g. “To what extent are your feelings about this issue or policy based on your fundamental beliefs about right and wrong?”).  When controlling for moral conviction, all other variables (e.g. demographics, political position, attitude importance, and attitude strength) were all insignificant predictors of social and political intolerance. I look forward to seeing how this replicates on a US sample and how political intolerance is operationalized. Perhaps something along the lines of liberal consideration of censoring Fox news or conservative publication of what many would consider private discussion would make good operationalizations of political intolerance as they mirror what we see in reality, where considerations of privacy, context, and free speech are considered secondary to partisanship. Moral conviction may underlie the hyperpartisanship that Politico talks about.

Hyperpartisanship and hypermoralism may be another instance of the effects of what evolutionary psychologist Deirdre Barrett calls “Supernormal Stimuli”. As the Wall Street Journal writes about her book:

As Ms. Barrett notes, modern life surrounds us with supernormal stimuli. An example: Humans evolved strong tastes for fats and sweets, tastes that conferred a reproductive advantage in the days when starvation was common. But these tastes can be a burden when we’re confronted with such supernormal stimuli as the 400-calorie Frappuccino at Starbucks. An evolutionary adaptation that once promised survival is more likely nowadays to produce Type 2 diabetes.

Ms. Barrett pushes her thesis too far at times, but her plain-spoken disquisition makes a strong case that supernormal stimuli “can help us understand the problems of modern civilization.”

One might even argue that supernormal stimuli—or perhaps our reactions to them—are the biggest problems faced by affluent societies.

In the case of hyperpartisanship and hypermoralism, our evolved moral senses, which allow human beings to cooperate, are now subject to the stimulus which is the 24 hour news cycle and the non-stop political campaign. Moral emotions are powerful forces, which are now activated routinely, rather than rarely.

If anybody has ideas on how to escape this cycle, I would love to hear them. Humanizing and getting to know the opposition, along the lines of intergroup contact theory, is an idea. Perhaps moral emotions can be activated against hyperpartisanship itself, rather than against individual ideologies. Or maybe with greater understanding, we can all learn to recognize supernormal moral stimuli and give them less power in our lives. Ideas welcome and I’m open to operationalizing particularly promising ideas as studies to be run on yourmorals.org.

– Ravi Iyer

Posted in book reviews, civil politics, consilience, hypermoralism, idealistic evil, incivility, joe wilson, news commentary, partisanship, political ideology, political psychology, yourmorals.org | 2 Comments »

The Psychology of the JournoList “Scandal”: Mirror Image Stereotypes

July 21st, 2010 by Ravi Iyer

As a regular reader of political blogs, I could not help but notice that a number of my favorite sites were writing about the same thing, specifically, their participation in a discussion group called JournoList, which included numerous media members such as Nate Silver of fivethirtyeight and Politico writer Ben Smith, both of whom I read with some regularity. These posts were prompted by the publication of numerous emails from this largely liberal group by a conservative blog, the Daily Caller, which recently ran this story (one of many on this topic):

On Journolist, there was rarely such thing as an honorable political disagreement between the left and right, though there were many disagreements on the left. In the view of many who’ve posted to the list-serv, conservatives aren’t simply wrong, they are evil. And while journalists are trained never to presume motive, Journolist members tend to assume that the other side is acting out of the darkest and most dishonorable motives.

Reading other people’s private emails evokes an embodied moral reaction in me. Maybe it’s motivated reasoning as a liberal myself, but I would hope that I’d find it similarly distasteful for a business to make money by posting the private emails of conservatives. Still, I think that the above paragraph is likely correct for some (not all) members of the list, along the lines of this wonderful post by Peter Ditto of UC-Irvine, concerning the ways that liberals and conservatives mirror each other in their negative attributions.  In it, he notes that a “mirror image pattern, two opposing sides in an ideological struggle having virtually identical stereotypes of each other, is a common characteristic in intergroup relations.” The idea is that when you find these mirror image perceptions, they are often more a function of partisanship and group conflict than reality.

It’s not hard to find quotes from conservatives that mirror the above observation of journolist members.  Consider this article entitled “Why does Obama hate America so badly?” My guess is that Democrats don’t hate the economy and Republicans don’t hate poor people, yet these mirror image negative attributions of malicious intent exist.

Here is the same story in graph form, using our yourmorals.org data, where liberals and conservatives rate both republicans and democrats on “warmth”…

and on “competence”….

Hardly surprising, but liberals think Republicans are cold and incompetent, while conservatives think Democrats are cold and incompetent.  (strangely, we generally think that we ourselves are both more warm and more competent than the average member of either party..:))

I’m sure that cherry picking any person’s email archive would lead to embarrassing material, but I would agree with Andrew Sullivan’s take on JournoList:

The far right is right on this: this collusion is corruption. It is no less corrupt than the comically propagandistic Fox News and the lock-step orthodoxy on the partisan right in journalism – but it is nonetheless corrupt…….

…..I’m glad Journo-list is over. It should never have been begun. I know many of its members are good and decent and fair-minded writers. But socialized groupthink is not the answer to what’s wrong with the media. It’s what’s already wrong with the media.

These mirror image negative perceptions are an inevitable part of intergroup conflict, so rather than morally judging the individuals involved for behavior that is likely quite common, I prefer to take this as a cautionary tale for all who want better policy. On both sides of the aisle, we should be seeking to recognize and reduce these biases, not amplify them through ideologically homogeneous discussions, such as what appeared to occur on JournoList.

– Ravi Iyer

Posted in civil politics, conservatives, journolist, liberals, news commentary, partisanship, political psychology, unpublished results, yourmorals.org | No Comments »